Is sectioning justifiable? The ethics of involuntary treatment.

Introduction
Depriving people with mental disorders of their liberty had been an unquestioned practise for centuries and even the 1845 Lunacy Act explicitly prohibited the discharge of patients deemed dangerous or unfit, together with removing their right to challenge their detention in court. Evermore, vesting the monopoly of coercion (and violence) to a legitimate authority is more or less nested within the foundations of our societies, justified by the aim of safeguarding justice, human rights and overall wellbeing. However, since 1845 many advances have occurred in the understanding and management of mental disorders, while the extent to which the state or other institutions should interfere with individuals’ freedom has been debated to different directions. The involuntary institutionalization and/or treatment of the mentally ill “who are a danger to themselves or to others,” although still common in most countries, has generated many heated discussions and hence aim of this essay is to discuss the ethical considerations intrinsic to such a proposition i.e.it is the right thing to do,” and those related to its practical and legal issues.


Defining Mental Disorders
One of the greatest challenges in psychiatry has been the definition of what actually constitutes a mental disorder and the absence of a solid definition has been the basis for arguments not only against ‘sectioning’ but also against psychiatry as a science altogether (c.f. Szasz[1]). Accounts range from those proposing a biomedical objective/factual-based definition to those considering mental disorders as products of subjective/value-judgments.[2-4]  
Currently, it seems that psychiatric diagnostic concepts are largely value-laden[3] and this wouldn’t matter as much if they weren’t a condition for involuntary interventions. For example even if cosmetic medicine is inherently value-laden, this does not usually pose any ethical problems as patients consent is prerequisite for any intervention.Therefore, one of the basic arguments against ‘sectioning’ has been its potential to be used as a tool for social control and political abuse. One great example is the diagnosis of ‘sluggish schizophrenia’ in USSR that confined people disagreeing with authority, as political dissent would “call in question the sanity of the one expressing it.[5] Similarly, the rates of schizophrenia diagnoses and misdiagnoses have been higher for African-Americans[6-9] and Metzl has argued that the 1968 DSM-II actually “functioned as an implicitly racist text because it mirrored the social context of its origins in ways that enabled users to knowingly or unknowingly pathologize protest as mental illness.”[10] Nonetheless, current and future research on psychiatric biomarkers and endophenotypes[11,12] may not only place the necessary safeguards but also transform our definitions.

Personhood and liberty
A common objection against ‘sectioning’ is that it violates individuals’ basic rights to freedom and self-determination, especially if we consider freedom as that from interference (known as ‘negative liberty’[13]). However, freedom can also be regarded as that of having the control and realizing one’s potential (‘positive liberty’[13]) and hence a mental disorder could nullify it. For instance, there is increasing evidence that people with unipolar depression exhibit negative processing biases in many cognitive domains which could consequently impair their judgment.[14] Therefore, ‘sectioning’ and involuntary treatment could actually safeguard and increase one’s positive liberty. Nevertheless, whether a state should foster the negative or positive liberties of individuals is a highly political question and lies outside the scope of this discussion.
On a more fundamental level, it should be noted that ‘sectioning’ might not violate one’s rights as they are ipso facto denied to him/her. Dennet argues that questioning one’s sanity entails the denial of his/her (moral) personhood[15] and therefore of both of his/her accountability and rights. Rights and responsibilities are not unconditional and not regarded so (c.f. children). Evermore, if an individual cannot be considered accountable, it is generally accepted that the state has the duty to prevent him/her from damaging others.
Perhaps, a way to bypass some ethical issues in a great number of cases would be the conclusion of an ‘Ulysses contract,’ by which individuals could decide in advance their management e.g. request or refusal of involuntary treatment. Advance directives don’t seem to affect future compulsory readmission rates[16] but may provide some ethical justification.




Paternalism and Autonomy
The argument of involuntary management of the mentally disordered is a paternalistic one and one major issue is the conflict between autonomy and beneficence, as a usual justification for an involuntary intervention is that this would be for the best interest of the individual. However, this conflict can be theoretically resolved.  Both Kant and John Mill, argued that one’s autonomy is conditional upon one’s rationality.[17] Hence, involuntary interventions restoring the former would also restore the later. Similarly, interfering with someone in order to assess his/her autonomy can also be justified. However, assessing one’s rationality and what is beneficial for him/her is a value-judgment depending on social norms and as such, increases the risk of abuse and assuming principles of strong paternalism (Strong paternalism in contrast to soft paternalism disregards the autonomy and capacity in favour of one’s best interest. The question of soft versus strong paternalism is again a political one.) For instance, the refusal of treatment could be regarded as evidence of impaired judgment while beneficence could be interpreted in terms of perceived medical needs rather than what the patient might wish. For a schizophrenic patient in remission, living with unacceptable side effects of medication and the risk of mental disintegration may not weight enough against ending his/her life, and this could be a rational judgment. Assuming global loss of rational capacity may have repercussions in one’s autonomy and wellbeing. Suicidality should not warrant coercion.[18]  
On the other hand, proponents of a more utilitarian socially-centred view could argue that involuntarily treating people with mental disorders is beneficial for the society as it may increase overall wellbeing and hence justifiable even at the cost of the individual. However, such a radical view could easily lead to totalitarianism.

The ‘Thank you’ argument
Finally, before considering some more practical issues, one argument that is often mentioned is that most people undergoing involuntary treatment retrospectively approve the decisions taken for them. However, in a national-wide study by Priebe et al.[19] only 40% of patients regaining capacity considered their detention justified. Moreover, Gardner et al.[20] found that despite accepting the necessity of detention, most people did not change their attitudes towards hospitalisation. Therefore it seems that the thank you argument is not very supportive.   


Overview of legislation
The legal frameworks vary considerably. For most countries in Europe, compulsory admission is legal only as a last resort option and the criteria that allow legal detention used by different countries can be grouped in three categories: First, there are frameworks in which the ‘need-for-treatment criterion’ is placed. Then there are countries which consider serious threat of harm to self and/or others as a prerequisite - the ‘dangerousness criterion.’ And finally there are countries like UK where either are used.[21] It is important to note that the use of different criteria ends up targeting and serving different people e.g. the dangerousness criterion might target younger men while the ‘need-to-treat’ older women.[22]
In England and Wales compulsory detention and/or treatment is covered by the Mental Health Act (1983), amended in 2007. The MHA criteria for detention required that one is suffering from a mental disorder and that detention is required in the interest of one's health or safety, or the safety of others. Detention is provisioned for emergency assessment (up to 72h; section 4), assessment with/without treatment (28 days, not renewable; s2) and for treatment up to 6 months (renewable after assessment; s3). Issues due to learning disability and alcohol or drug dependence are excluded. In order to safeguard patients rights, the MHA also includes provisions for independent advocates, immediate access to information and the right to appeal against their detention. The amended MHA makes it possible for compulsory treatment to be given in the community too (s17) but the ethics are similar and won’t be discusses separately. (Community treatment orders even if more restrictive (in terms of duration) were proposed as a means of preventing future involuntary admissions however recent empirical evidence is not supportive.[37] In principle the ethics of CTOs do not differ but special issues are discussed in [38].) Other crucial details will be discussed together with other important issues. 

Treatment and Capacity
One fundamental conflict in medicine is that of beneficence versus the principle of primum non nocere. There is no perfect intervention and the risk of harmful side effects is always weighted against the probability of achieving a favourable outcome.  From the practitioner point of view this is usually resolved by transferring the burden of this judgment to the patient via an informed consent. However, the situation is radically different when the practitioner has denied the patient’s autonomy and takes the responsibility of deciding against one’s will. But, is it morally acceptable to carry a potentially harmful action when it is resisted? Most times this is outweighed by overall positive outcomes but the action per se might not be necessarily justified. For instance, it is to some extend reasonable to disregard a paranoid delusion that a treatment is lethal, but what if the basis of the refusal is the experience of side effects? The European Committee for the Prevention of Torture and Inhuman or Degrading Treatment or Punishment explicitly states that  “the admission of a person to a psychiatric establishment on an involuntary basis should not be construed as authorising treatment without his consent.[23] However, the current legal framework allows involuntary detention/treatment even when one has capacity and although doctor-patient negotiation is promoted, this is not guaranteed: “The consent of a patient shall not be required for any medical treatment given to him for mental disorder from which he is suffering”(s63). Evermore, current empirical evidence testifies for only “limited clinical and social gainsafter involuntary treatment.[24] Additionally, according to a study by Owen et al.[25] 6% of in-patients were detained while having capacity, and the only positive association with that group was treatment refusal.  Side effects can be permanent, although the extent to which involuntary treatment contributes to disability has not been properly characterised and may have serious implications with regards this group of patients.  Interestingly, Carpenter et al.[26] showed that using educational interventions (teaching, using computer programs etc.), can lead to significant increases in the decision making capacity of schizophrenic patients, and it could be argued that many involuntary admission/interventions could be prevented by spending more time with the patient. 
Probably because of such considerations, for psychosurgery or the surgical implantation of hormones the MHA requires both patient's consent and permission from an independent psychiatrist, while for non-urgent ECT, either consent or a permission in the absence of advanced decision will suffice. Nevertheless, even if such provisions seem sound, they are in principle contradictory as there is nothing fundamentally special about these treatments and it could be argued (using the principle of proportionality) that similar restrictive criteria should be applied for any intervention. 

Treatability
To justify involuntary admissions/interventions within the concept of paternalism, many legal frameworks have the condition that interventions are likely to improve or prevent one’s deterioration. To this effect the original MHA stated that long-term compulsion could be used only if the treatment was ‘likely to alleviate or prevent a deterioration’(s3) avoiding so the detention of people that would not benefit. Of course this was associated with practical challenges in determining whether and which therapy would have positive outcomes, but from a human rights approach prevented the unconstrained use of trial and error.[27] However, with the 2007 amendment this ‘treatability test’ was replaced with the requirement that “appropriate medical treatment is available.” This put emphasis on the general purpose of interventions rather than patient-specific disease outcomes and many argued that this was a politically driven decision so that offenders with mental disorders could be detained (theoretically indefinitely) protecting so the public; as interventions with the potential to reduce symptoms (e.g. containment) would appear acceptable.[27,28] Hence, albeit MHA has been grounded with paternalistic aims, the increased potential of  “social control through the agency of psychiatry”[29]  has many ethical implications.

Is it ‘dangerous’?
The dangerousness criterion was born out of the need for fair decisions and protecting the public; but the absence of absolutely accurate and valid instruments for the prediction of violent behaviour introduces an important ethical dilemma: can the prevention of violence be traded with the unnecessary compulsion of others? It is estimated that by using the most effective instruments, in order to prevent one act of violence, 3.5 people need to be detained.[30] If the act is to cause serious injury, then the theoretical number rises to 15[30] and to several thousands for a homicide.[31] Yet, even with a utilitarian approach it is difficult to define an acceptable ‘equation.’ It is noted that “more people die because of antipsychotics than are killed by people as a result of their mental disorder.[27] The negative consequences of ‘unnecessary detention’ have not been characterized but could involve treatment side effects, avoidance of services, and experience of stigma and discrimination. As Phelan and Link have noted, the use of this criterion may also increase the stigmatization of all mental health patients as dangerous and violent[32] affecting so a larger number of people; who anyway are more likely to be victims than perpetrators.[33] On the other hand, when this criterion is used obligatorily it can actually lead to delayed treatment and therefore worse outcomes.[34] 
There is some merit for a dangerousness criterion but it is questionable whether it’s current use is justifiable especially when used without considering the ‘need-for-treatment’ criterion or even patients’ capacity. After all, “psychiatrists are doctors and their primary role is to improve patients’ health, superseding issues of public protection.[35]  

Concluding remarks
Expectedly, a definitive answer to the question of whether the discussed proposition is right or not cannot be given. If at all, although, the discussion was already limited by unavoidable constraints in space, it can be safely concluded that this question is interwoven with issues related to the foundations of psychiatry, i.e. the value-laden definitions of mental disorders and beneficence; political-philosophical issues such as those between negative versus positive liberties and soft versus strong paternalism; human rights and the potential for political abuse or social control; issues related to treatability and dangerousness assessment; the justification of trade-offs and the discrepancies between all these. These issues were not exhausted, yet, it became clear that current practices are far from ideal and more investigations and open discussions are needed. Furthermore, one should investigate aspects of care and policies that may not be directly relevant but which may have important implications for patients, their autonomy and mental health care, such as the experience of coercion and the effects of deinstitutionalization. Howbeit, laws and practice should reflect what is already stated in the legal literature: “the mentally disordered are not objects of protection but subjects equal to the healthy, who enjoy the same guarantees for respect of their personhood […] Individuals with any kind of limitation should be recognized a fundamental social right to enjoy measures ensuring their autonomy and their integration in social, financial and political affairs.”[36]







References
1. Szasz TS. The myth of mental illness. Am Psychol 1960;15:113.
2. Brulde B. Wakefield's hybrid account of mental disorder. World Psychiatry 2007;6:163-4.
3. Fulford KW, Broome M, Stanghellini G, Thornton T. Looking with both eyes open: fact and value in psychiatric diagnosis? World Psychiatry 2005;4:78-86.
4. Wakefield JC. The concept of mental disorder: diagnostic implications of the harmful dysfunction analysis. World Psychiatry 2007;6:149-56.
5. Wilkinson G. Political dissent and "sluggish" schizophrenia in the Soviet Union. Br Med J (Clin Res Ed) 1986;293:641-2.
6. Mukherjee S, Shukla S, Woodle J, Rosen AM, Olarte S. Misdiagnosis of schizophrenia in bipolar patients: a multiethnic comparison. Am J Psychiatry 1983;140:1571-4.
7. Simon RJ, Fleiss JL, Gurland BJ, Stiller PR, Sharpe L. Depression and schizophrenia in hospitalized black and white mental patients. Arch Gen Psychiatry 1973;28:509-12.
8. Strakowski SM, Shelton RC, Kolbrener ML. The effects of race and comorbidity on clinical diagnosis in patients with psychosis. J Clin Psychiatry 1993;54:96-102.
9. Strakowski SM, Lonczak HS, Sax KW, West SA, Crist A, Mehta R, et al. The effects of race on diagnosis and disposition from a psychiatric emergency service. J Clin Psychiatry 1995;56:101-7.
10. Metzl J. The Protest Psychosis: How Schizophrenia Became a Black Disease.: Beacon Press, 2010.
11. Gottesman II, Gould TD. The endophenotype concept in psychiatry: etymology and strategic intentions. Am J Psychiatry 2003;160:636-45.
12. Boksa P. A way forward for research on biomarkers for psychiatric disorders. J Psychiatry Neurosci 2013;38:75-7.
13. Berlin I. Two Concepts of Liberty. In: Anonymous Four essays on liberty.: Oxford University Press, Oxford Paperbacks, 1969.
14. Everaert J, Koster EH, Derakshan N. The combined cognitive bias hypothesis in depression. Clin Psychol Rev 2012;32:413-24.
15. Dennett D. Conditions of personhood. In: Oksenberg-Rorty A, editor. The Identities of Persons. : University of California Press, 1984: 175.
16. Papageorgiou A, King M, Janmohamed A, Davidson O, Dawson J. Advance directives for patients compulsorily admitted to hospital with serious mental illness. Randomised controlled trial. Br J Psychiatry 2002;181:513-9.
17. Christman J. Autonomy in Moral and Political Philosophy, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Spring 2011 Edition.
18. Callaghan S, Ryan C, Kerridge I. Risk of suicide is insufficient warrant for coercive treatment for mental illness. Int J Law Psychiatry 2013;36:374-85.
19. Priebe S, Katsakou C, Amos T, Leese M, Morriss R, Rose D, et al. Patients' views and readmissions 1 year after involuntary hospitalisation. Br J Psychiatry 2009;194:49-54.
20. Gardner W, Lidz CW, Hoge SK, Monahan J, Eisenberg MM, Bennett NS, et al. Patients' revisions of their beliefs about the need for hospitalization. Am J Psychiatry 1999;156:1385-91.
21. Salize HJ, Dreßing H, Peitz M. Compulsory admission and involuntary treatment of mentally ill patients-legislation and practice in EU-member states. Central Institute of Mental Health Research Project Final Report, Mannheim, Germany 2002;15.
22. Segal SP. Civil commitment standards and patient mix in England/Wales, Italy, and the United States. Am J Psychiatry 1989;146:187-93.
23. CPT Standards European Committee for the Prevention of Torture CPT/Inf/E (2002) 1, Rev 2004, p. 57, para 41. IN Bartlett P. 'The necessity must be convincingly shown to exist': standards for compulsory treatment for mental disorder under the Mental Health Act 1983. Med Law Rev 2011;19:514-47.
24. Priebe S, Katsakou C, Yeeles K, Amos T, Morriss R, Wang D, et al. Predictors of clinical and social outcomes following involuntary hospital admission: a prospective observational study. Eur Arch Psychiatry Clin Neurosci 2011;261:377-86.
25. Owen GS, Szmukler G, Richardson G, David AS, Hayward P, Rucker J, et al. Mental capacity and psychiatric in-patients: implications for the new mental health law in England and Wales. Br J Psychiatry 2009;195:257-63.
26. Carpenter WT,Jr, Gold JM, Lahti AC, Queern CA, Conley RR, Bartko JJ, et al. Decisional capacity for informed consent in schizophrenia research. Arch Gen Psychiatry 2000;57:533-8.
27. Bartlett P. 'The necessity must be convincingly shown to exist': standards for compulsory treatment for mental disorder under the Mental Health Act 1983. Med Law Rev 2011;19:514-47.
28. Pickersgill M. How Personality Became Treatable: The Mutual Constitution of Clinical Knowledge and Mental Health Law. Social Studies of Science 2012.
29. Moncrieff J. The politics of a new Mental Health Act. Br J Psychiatry 2003;183:8-9.
30. Buchanan A. Risk of violence by psychiatric patients: beyond the "actuarial versus clinical" assessment debate. Psychiatr Serv 2008;59:184-90.
31. Morgan JF. Giving up the Culture of Blame: risk assessment and risk management in psychiatric practice. Royal College of Psychiatrists 2007.
32. Phelan JC, Link BG. The growing belief that people with mental illnesses are violent: the role of the dangerousness criterion for civil commitment. Soc Psychiatry Psychiatr Epidemiol 1998;33 Suppl 1:S7-12.
33. Brekke JS, Prindle C, Bae SW, Long JD. Risks for individuals with schizophrenia who are living in the community. Psychiatr Serv 2001;52:1358-66.
34. Large MM, Nielssen O, Ryan CJ, Hayes R. Mental health laws that require dangerousness for involuntary admission may delay the initial treatment of schizophrenia. Soc Psychiatry Psychiatr Epidemiol 2008;43:251-6.
35. Mental Health Law subcommittee of the Royal College of Psychiatrists.    Response to the Government’s White Paper ‘Reforming the Mental Health   Act.’ London; Royal College of Psychiatrists, 2001. IN Morgan JF. Giving up the Culture of Blame: risk assessment and risk management in psychiatric practice. Royal College of Psychiatrists 2007.
36. Alexakis, Y. O thesmos tis dhikastikis symparastasis [The institution of judicial support]. Klimaka-Afieromata 2004;8:6-19. (in Greek)
37. Burns T, Rugkasa J, Molodynski A, Dawson J, Yeeles K, Vazquez-Montes M, et al. Community treatment orders for patients with psychosis (OCTET): a randomised controlled trial. Lancet 2013;381:1627-33.
38. Munetz MR, Galon PA, Frese FJ,3rd. The ethics of mandatory community treatment. J Am Acad Psychiatry Law 2003;31:173-83.

No comments

Leave a Reply

Blogroll

About Me

My photo
Αθανάσιος Αλεξανδρής